Political Naturalism
June 11, 2014
Aristotle lays the foundations for
his political theory in Politics book I by arguing that the city-state
and political rule are “natural.” The argument begins with a schematic,
quasi-historical account of the development of the city-state out of simpler
communities. First, individual human beings combined in pairs because they
could not exist apart. The male and female joined in order to reproduce, and
the master and slave came together for self-preservation. The natural master
used his intellect to rule, and the natural slave employed his body to labor.
Second, the household arose naturally from these primitive communities in order
to serve everyday needs. Third, when several households combined for further
needs a village emerged also according to nature. Finally, “the complete
community, formed from several villages, is a city-state, which at once attains
the limit of self-sufficiency, roughly speaking. It comes to be for the sake of
life, and exists for the sake of the good life” (I.2.1252b27–30).
Aristotle defends three claims about
nature and the city-state: First, the city-state exists by nature, because it
comes to be out of the more primitive natural associations and it serves as
their end, because it alone attains self-sufficiency (1252b30-1253a1). Second,
human beings are by nature political animals, because nature, which does
nothing in vain, has equipped them with speech, which enables them to
communicate moral concepts such as justice which are formative of the household
and city-state (1253a1-18). Third, the city-state is naturally prior to the
individuals, because individuals cannot perform their natural functions apart
from the city-state, since they are not self-sufficient (1253a18-29). These
three claims are conjoined, however, with a fourth: the city-state is a
creation of human intelligence. “Therefore, everyone naturally has the impulse
for such a [political] community, but the person who first established [it] is
the cause of very great benefits.” This great benefactor is evidently the
lawgiver (nomothetês), for the legal system of the city-state makes human
beings just and virtuous and lifts them from the savagery and bestiality in
which they would otherwise languish (1253a29–39).
Aristotle's political naturalism
presents the difficulty that he does not explain how he is using the term
“nature” (phusis). In the Physics nature is understood as an
internal principle of motion or rest (see III.1.192b8–15). (For discussion of
nature see Aristotle's Physics.) If the city-state were natural in this
sense, it would resemble a plant or an animal which grows naturally to maturity
out of a seed. However, this cannot be reconciled with the important role which
Aristotle also assigns to the lawgiver as the one who established the
city-state. For on Aristotle's theory a thing either exists by nature or by
craft; it cannot do both. (This difficulty is posed by David Keyt.) Aristotle
can seemingly escape this dilemma only if it is supposed that he speaks of the
city-state as “natural” in another sense of the term. For example, he might
mean that it is “natural” in the extended sense that it arises from human
natural inclinations (to live in communities) for the sake of human natural
ends, but that it remains unfinished until a lawgiver provides it with a
constitution. (This solution was proposed by Ernest Barker and is defended more
recently by Fred Miller and Trevor Saunders.)